Semantic internalism is a mistake

Autor

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.38.08

Słowa kluczowe:

internalism, externalism, one-factor dimensional account of representation, mental representation, Fodor, methodological solipsism

Abstrakt

The concept of narrow content is still under discussion in the debate over mental representation. In the paper, one-factor dimensional accounts of representation are analyzed, particularly the case of Fodor's methodological solipsism. In methodological solipsism, semantic properties of content are arguably eliminated in favor of syntactic ones. If “narrow content” means content properties independent of external factors to a system (as in Segal's view), the concept of content becomes elusive. Moreover, important conceptual problems with one-factor dimensional account are pointed out as a result of analysis arguments presented by J. Searle, S. Harnad and T. Burge. Furthermore, these problems are illustrated with psychological and ethological examples. Although understanding content as partially independent from contextual factors allows theorists to preserve content properties, it seems that understanding content in total abstraction from external factors of these properties is implausible. As a result, internalism is rejected in favor of externalism.

Bibliografia

Block, Ned. 1987. “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1): 615–78. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00558.x.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00558.x

Burge, Tyler. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1): 73–121. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.x.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.x

Carnap, R. 1947. Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Chalmers, David J. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Chalmers, David J. 2004. “Epistemic Two-Dimensional Semantics.” Philosophical Studies 118 (1/2): 153–226. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000019546.17135.e0.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHIL.0000019546.17135.e0

Copeland, B. Jack. 1993. Artificial Intelligence: A Philosophical Introduction. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Copi, Irving, and Carl Cohen. 2002. Introduction to Logic. 11thed. Upper Saddle River N.J.: Prentice Hall.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Dennett, Daniel C. 1987. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Dennett, Daniel C. 1991. Consciousness Explained. New York: Back Bay Books / Little Brown and Company.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Field, Hartry. 1978. “Mental Representation.” Erkenntnis 13: 9–61.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00160888

Fodor, Jerry A. 1975. The Language of Thought. 1sted. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Company.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Fodor, Jerry A. 1980. “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1): 63–63. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00001771.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00001771

Fodor, Jerry A. 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/5684.001.0001

Fodor, Jerry A. 2008. LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford University Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199548774.001.0001

Fodor, Jerry A., M F Garrett, E C Walker, and C H Parkes. 1980. “Against Definitions.” Cognition 8 (3): 263–367.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(80)90008-6

Griffiths, Paul Edmund. 2002. “What Is Innateness?” The Monist 85 (1).
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/monist20028518

Gulick, R. van. 2001. “Reduction, Emergence and Other Recent Options on the Mind/body Problem. A Philosophic Overview.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 (9–10): 1–34.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Harnad, Stevan. 1990. “The Symbol Grounding Problem.” Physica D 42: 335–46.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/0167-2789(90)90087-6

Hauser, Larry. 1997. “Searle’s Chinese Box: Debunking the Chinese Room Argument.” Minds and Machines 7 (2): 199–226.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008255830248

Heath, J. 2015. “Methodological Individualism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Jadacki, Jacek. 2001. Spór O Granice Języka : Elementy Semiotyki Logicznej I Metodologii. Warszawa: Wydawn. Naukowe Semper.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Maruszewski, Tomasz. 1983. Analiza Procesów Poznawczych Jednostki W Świetle Idealizacyjnej Teorii Nauki. Poznań: Wydawn. Nauk. Uniwersytetu im. A. Mickiewicza.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Pitt, David. 2013. “Mental Representation.” Edited by Edward N Zalta. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/mental-representation/
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Poczobut, Robert. 2007. “Eksternalizm Treści Umysłowej a Superweniencja.” Kognitywistyka I Media W Edukacji2 9 (1): 82–106.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Preston, John, and Mark Bishop. 2002. Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford; New York: Clarendon Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar

Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “The Meaning of Meaning.” In Philosophical Papers, Vol. II : Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625251

Samuels, Richard. 2002. “Nativism in Cognitive Science.” Mind and Language 17 (3): 233–65. doi:10.1111/1468-0017.00197.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00197

Samuels, Richard. 2004. “Innateness in Cognitive Science.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (3): 136–41. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.01.010.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2004.01.010

Searle, John R. 1980. “Minds, Brains, and Programs.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3): 1–19. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00005756.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00005756

Searle, John R. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge / New York: Cambridge University Press.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139173452

Segal, Gabriel. 2000. A Slim Book about Narrow Content. Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press. http://www.worldcat.org/title/slim-book-about-narrow-content/oclc/42771559&referer=brief_results
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/6275.001.0001

Stich, Stephen P. 1980. “Paying the Price for Methodological Solipsism.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1): 97. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00002016.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00002016

Yablo, S. 1999. “Intrinsicness.” Philosophical Topics 26 (1/2): 479–505.
Zobacz w Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics1999261/234

Opublikowane

2017-09-30

Jak cytować

Bielecka, K. (2017). Semantic internalism is a mistake. Hybris, 38(3), 123–146. https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.38.08