Semantic internalism is a mistake

Authors

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.38.08

Keywords:

internalism, externalism, one-factor dimensional account of representation, mental representation, Fodor, methodological solipsism

Abstract

The concept of narrow content is still under discussion in the debate over mental representation. In the paper, one-factor dimensional accounts of representation are analyzed, particularly the case of Fodor's methodological solipsism. In methodological solipsism, semantic properties of content are arguably eliminated in favor of syntactic ones. If “narrow content” means content properties independent of external factors to a system (as in Segal's view), the concept of content becomes elusive. Moreover, important conceptual problems with one-factor dimensional account are pointed out as a result of analysis arguments presented by J. Searle, S. Harnad and T. Burge. Furthermore, these problems are illustrated with psychological and ethological examples. Although understanding content as partially independent from contextual factors allows theorists to preserve content properties, it seems that understanding content in total abstraction from external factors of these properties is implausible. As a result, internalism is rejected in favor of externalism.

References

Block, Ned. 1987. “Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10 (1): 615–78. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00558.x.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00558.x

Burge, Tyler. 1979. “Individualism and the Mental.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1): 73–121. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.x.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.x

Carnap, R. 1947. Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
View in Google Scholar

Chalmers, David J. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
View in Google Scholar

Chalmers, David J. 2004. “Epistemic Two-Dimensional Semantics.” Philosophical Studies 118 (1/2): 153–226. doi:10.1023/B:PHIL.0000019546.17135.e0.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHIL.0000019546.17135.e0

Copeland, B. Jack. 1993. Artificial Intelligence: A Philosophical Introduction. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.
View in Google Scholar

Copi, Irving, and Carl Cohen. 2002. Introduction to Logic. 11thed. Upper Saddle River N.J.: Prentice Hall.
View in Google Scholar

Dennett, Daniel C. 1987. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
View in Google Scholar

Dennett, Daniel C. 1991. Consciousness Explained. New York: Back Bay Books / Little Brown and Company.
View in Google Scholar

Field, Hartry. 1978. “Mental Representation.” Erkenntnis 13: 9–61.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00160888

Fodor, Jerry A. 1975. The Language of Thought. 1sted. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell Company.
View in Google Scholar

Fodor, Jerry A. 1980. “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1): 63–63. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00001771.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00001771

Fodor, Jerry A. 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/5684.001.0001

Fodor, Jerry A. 2008. LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford University Press.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199548774.001.0001

Fodor, Jerry A., M F Garrett, E C Walker, and C H Parkes. 1980. “Against Definitions.” Cognition 8 (3): 263–367.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(80)90008-6

Griffiths, Paul Edmund. 2002. “What Is Innateness?” The Monist 85 (1).
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/monist20028518

Gulick, R. van. 2001. “Reduction, Emergence and Other Recent Options on the Mind/body Problem. A Philosophic Overview.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 (9–10): 1–34.
View in Google Scholar

Harnad, Stevan. 1990. “The Symbol Grounding Problem.” Physica D 42: 335–46.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/0167-2789(90)90087-6

Hauser, Larry. 1997. “Searle’s Chinese Box: Debunking the Chinese Room Argument.” Minds and Machines 7 (2): 199–226.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008255830248

Heath, J. 2015. “Methodological Individualism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
View in Google Scholar

Jadacki, Jacek. 2001. Spór O Granice Języka : Elementy Semiotyki Logicznej I Metodologii. Warszawa: Wydawn. Naukowe Semper.
View in Google Scholar

Maruszewski, Tomasz. 1983. Analiza Procesów Poznawczych Jednostki W Świetle Idealizacyjnej Teorii Nauki. Poznań: Wydawn. Nauk. Uniwersytetu im. A. Mickiewicza.
View in Google Scholar

Pitt, David. 2013. “Mental Representation.” Edited by Edward N Zalta. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/mental-representation/
View in Google Scholar

Poczobut, Robert. 2007. “Eksternalizm Treści Umysłowej a Superweniencja.” Kognitywistyka I Media W Edukacji2 9 (1): 82–106.
View in Google Scholar

Preston, John, and Mark Bishop. 2002. Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence. Oxford; New York: Clarendon Press.
View in Google Scholar

Putnam, Hilary. 1975. “The Meaning of Meaning.” In Philosophical Papers, Vol. II : Mind, Language, and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625251

Samuels, Richard. 2002. “Nativism in Cognitive Science.” Mind and Language 17 (3): 233–65. doi:10.1111/1468-0017.00197.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00197

Samuels, Richard. 2004. “Innateness in Cognitive Science.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8 (3): 136–41. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.01.010.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2004.01.010

Searle, John R. 1980. “Minds, Brains, and Programs.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3): 1–19. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00005756.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00005756

Searle, John R. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge / New York: Cambridge University Press.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139173452

Segal, Gabriel. 2000. A Slim Book about Narrow Content. Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press. http://www.worldcat.org/title/slim-book-about-narrow-content/oclc/42771559&referer=brief_results
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/6275.001.0001

Stich, Stephen P. 1980. “Paying the Price for Methodological Solipsism.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1): 97. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00002016.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00002016

Yablo, S. 1999. “Intrinsicness.” Philosophical Topics 26 (1/2): 479–505.
View in Google Scholar DOI: https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics1999261/234

Downloads

Published

2017-09-30

How to Cite

Bielecka, K. (2017). Semantic internalism is a mistake. Hybris, 38(3), 123–146. https://doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.38.08